The Challenges of Philosophical Writing
The aim of the assignments on your philosophy training
is to get you doing philosophy. But what is philosophy,
and the way is it to be completed? The answer is complicated.
Philosophers are often encouraged by one or greater of what
we might name the “Big Questions,” which includes: How must
we stay? Is there free will? How will we realize anything?
Or, What is reality? While philosophers do no longer agree amongst
themselves on either the range of right philosophical
questions or the right techniques of answering them, they
do agree that merely expressing one’s private evaluations
on arguable subjects like those isn't always doing philosophy.
Rather, philosophers insist at the technique of first reaching
clarity about the exact question being requested, after which
presenting answers supported via clear, logically structured
arguments.
An ideal philosophical argument have to lead the reader in
simple logical steps from manifestly genuine premises to an
unobvious conclusion. A negative argument is an objection
that tries to reveal that a declare, theory, or argument is
wrong; if it does so effectively, we say that it refutes
it. A high quality argument attempts to aid a claim or principle,
for instance, the view that there's true free will,
or the view that we have to never devour animals. Positive
philosophical arguments about the Big Questions which are
ideal are extraordinarily hard to assemble, and philosophers
inquisitive about formulating or criticizing such arguments
usually become discussing other questions that can at the beginning
seem pedantic or contrived. These questions motivate
philosophers due to the fact they seem, after investigation, to
be logically related to the Big Questions and to shed
light on them. So, for instance, whilst trying to answer
Big Questions like those above, philosophers might locate
themselves discussing questions like (respectively): When
wouldn't it be morally permissible to push a person into the
path of a dashing trolley? What is a cause? Do I know
that I have palms? Is there an external international? While
arguing approximately these questions may appear stupid or pointless,
the satisfactions of philosophy are often derived from,
first, coming across and explicating how they're logically
connected to the Big Questions, and 2nd, constructing
and protecting philosophical arguments to reply them in
flip. Good philosophy proceeds with modest, careful and
clean steps.
Structuring a Philosophy Paper
Philosophy assignments typically ask you to keep in mind
a few thesis or argument, regularly a thesis or argument that
has been presented via another philosopher (a thesis is
a declare that can be proper or fake). Given this thesis or
argument, you may be asked to do one or more of the
following: give an explanation for it, offer a controversy in guide of
it, offer an objection to it, guard towards an objection
to it, compare the arguments for and towards it, talk
what results it'd have, determine whether
a few different thesis or argument commits one to it (i.E.,
if I regular the alternative thesis or argument, could I be
rationally required to accept this one due to the fact I receive
the other one?), or determine whether or not a few different view
can be held consistently with it. No depend which of
these tasks you are requested to finish, your paper need to
normally meet the subsequent structural requirements:
Begin with the aid of formulating your unique thesis. State
your thesis virtually and concisely on your introduction
so that your reader knows what your paper sets
out to acquire. Get to the point quickly and with out
digression. Don’t attempt to introduce your argument
inside a grand historical narrative, as an instance. Your
thesis does not need to be similar to any thesis
stated inside the undertaking, despite the fact that in a few cases it
can be.
GOOD WRITING EXAMPLE
Jen turned into an wonderful philosophy writer who
acquired the following task:
Evaluate Smith’s argument for the declare
that people lack unfastened will.
Jen decided earlier than she started writing her paper
that Smith’s argument in the long run fails because it
trades on an ambiguity. Accordingly, she commenced
her paper with the subsequent sentence:
In this paper, I will refute Smith’s argument towards
the lifestyles of free will via showing that it trades on an
ambiguity.
Jen’s thesis, then, was that Smith’s argument is
invalid because it trades on an ambiguity – and she
stated it surely right at the beginning of her paper.
Note that Jen need no longer say something in any respect approximately
the fact or falsity of the thesis that human beings lack
unfastened will; despite the fact that Smith’s argument for it's miles invalid,
it'd nevertheless be proper that humans lack unfastened will.
SPOOR WRITING EXAMPLE
In solution to the formerly cited
task, George wrote a paper arguing that
there has been free will, since George
become himself privy to making all sorts of free
picks each day. His conclusion became that
Smith’s argument (which he had now not explained,
and cited handiest at the quit of the paper) ought to
be fake, in view that there's loose will.
George’s professor requested him to rewrite, telling
him that he had didn't engage with Smith’s
argument inside the first draft. Here is an excerpt
from George’s much less-than-a success rewrite…
… Smith says on p.Nine, “The truth of causal
determinism having been installed via this argument
from removal, we shall circulate on to show
incompatibilism.” Smith then says that the supply of
an agent’s moves is some occasion that befell before he
changed into even born. If an occasion took place earlier than a person became
born, it can't be a manufactured from his choices. Therefore
incompatibilism is actual. On p.10, Smith addresses the
objection that…
George does not nicely explain and examine
the common sense of Smith’s argument (a philosophy
paper), however instead reviews what Smith says and
the manner in which it seems in the text (a book
record). In the first sentence George fees
Smith without delay wherein there is no want to do
so, and he provides no clarification of Smith’s
sentence or the technical phrases in it that indicates
that George without a doubt knows it. In his 2nd
sentence, George just follows Smith’s text even as
paraphrasing it. In his 1/3, George can be
attempting to: (i) truly paraphrase Smith, or
(ii) paraphrase and suggest Smith’s declare, or (iii)
make his personal personal point – but to the reader
it's far left ambiguous what George thinks Smith’s
view is and what George’s own view is.
If you use a declare that your
reader might find dubious,
then you definately must attempt to give the
reader convincing reasons for
accepting it.
Evidence
From your philosophy trainer, a request for proof
for a declare is generally a request for an issue, or
for a higher argument. While philosophers may additionally from
time to time employ medical generalizations or
results, they typically avoid the messy and specialised
commercial enterprise of accumulating and arguing approximately empirical information,
and confine their investigations to their armchairs. This
is a wide generalization; once in a while empirical proof
from psychology, physics or different fields of inquiry can be
positioned to proper use in philosophical arguments. But if you
do use such proof from some other place, by no means simply expect
that it solves your philosophical query: be cautious to
provide an explanation for precisely why it's miles relevant and exactly what we can
conclude from it, and do make sure which you as it should be
record what the scientists have to inform us.
Philosophers nevertheless find loads to argue about even if
they positioned empirical questions apart. For one element, the
query of what kind of empirical evidence could be
needed to decide the answer to a question might itself be
a non-empirical query that philosophers discuss. For
another, philosophers spend quite a few time discussing how
distinctive claims (which may be empirical) relate logically
to every other. For instance, a common philosophical
mission is to show how or more perspectives can not be held
constantly with each other, or to expose that although
perspectives are regular with each other, they together
entail an incredible 0.33 claim. If a hit, this kind of
argument, known as a reductio advert absurdum or reductio for
brief, suggests that we've got purpose to reject at the least one of
its premises.
EXAMPLE OF A REDUCTIO
sGOOD USE OF EXAMPLES
Jen is arguing for the thesis that it is permissible
for me to perform some moves that have
foreknown side results which it wouldn’t be
permissible to aim at immediately. She uses examples
efficiently each to explain the notion of a
“foreknown facet-effect,” and to help deliver our
intuitions to endure on her thesis:
A foreknown aspect-effect of an action is an event or country
of affairs that one does no longer intention at whilst one acts, but
that one knows will (possibly) result from one’s action.
For instance, I decide to drive to class if you want to store
time. I recognize that my riding will leave the parking
space in the front of my house empty. The empty parking
space is a foreknown aspect-effect of my action: I don’t
purpose at it, due to the fact my purpose is most effective to get myself to school
quicker.
…
To help prove my factor approximately the distinction in
permissibility between ambitions and foreknown aspect-outcomes,
I will use the following hypothetical instance: Bill
the bomber pilot has decided to bomb an important
munitions manufacturing facility. Bill knows that the factory is subsequent
to a medical institution, and that about 1,000 civilian casualties
are probably. But bombing the factory will bring an early
defeat to the enemy with the aid of cutting their fingers glide. This
will demoralize them and assist end the warfare. Bill’s
action, I contend, may be permissible. Now I’ll simply
regulate the case slightly: Bob the bomber pilot has determined
to bomb a munitions factory. Bob is aware of that the
factory is next to a health facility, and that about 1,000
civilian casualties are possibly. In fact, bombing the factory
is the exceptional way to result in this type of high wide variety of
casualties, and this is why Bob has decided to bomb
there. Bringing about this many civilian casualties will
assist weaken the enemy’s resolve and thereby bring an
early end to the warfare. (It may even have a aspect-impact of
reducing their arms float). I contend that Bob’s motion is
truly impermissible.
Examples like these might deliver clean moral
intuitions, and if Jen can assemble an example
in which she can persuade us that it's far certainly
clear that something could be approved as a
foreknown aspect-effect but not as an purpose, she will
have an amazing argument for her thesis.
There are a couple of kinds of “proof” that you should
now not use in philosophy papers: Do no longer argue that a declare
is true, or is in all likelihood to be genuine, just due to the fact a person of
high-quality authority believed it. Authorities may be incorrect, and
philosophers want to see the arguments for a view. And do
no longer argue from what the dictionary says about something.
If the dictionary defines reality as “correspondence with
reality”, you can not use this as an argument that truth
is correspondence with fact due to the fact either you're
treating the dictionary as an authority, or you're citing
it as a reporter of commonplace usage. But philosophers don’t
want to recognize what the majority think or expect approximately
what reality is, they want to recognise what's in reality the
case! (N.B.: you could additionally be misled while you seek advice from
the dictionary because a few words have technical,
philosophical meanings inside the concern that vary from
their everyday utilization.)
Sources
You may freely use the arguments of different philosophers
for your papers so long as you credit score them appropriately,
and also do your personal philosophical questioning. Again, if
you need to provide an explanation for someone else’s argument, you have to
do so for your own words and in step with your personal clean
knowledge of the logical steps worried in it. It is also
extraordinarily vital that when you give an explanation for the arguments
of different philosophers, you interpret them charitably. This
does no longer suggest which you are barred from criticizing them,
but alternatively which you have to interpret every creator as protecting
the most powerful possible argument constant with what they
have written. If a truth seeker’s argument seems glaringly
incorrect, then you definitely likely do now not apprehend it well.
Even if a truth seeker’s argument appears right, you must
take extremely good care to avoid difficult their argument with any
other argument that sounds similar to it.
You can help yourself to avoid these difficulties by using education
your self to examine philosophy articles extraordinarily slowly and
cautiously if you want to apprehend the perfect steps of the
author’s argument. It isn't uncommon to should examine a
philosophy article numerous instances in order to grasp its information.
Philosophy is tough through nature: to avoid making matters
even more difficult, ensure that the argument for your paper is
truly as clean and smooth to understand as feasible!
If you are requested to provide an issue or an objection and
the undertaking does now not require that it be your own, then
you could usually use one that you have found out in elegance
or from the readings, with proper credit score. In this case, you
need to now not handiest placed the argument for your personal words
and within the logical shape that appears clearest to you, however additionally
see whether or not there is any way wherein you may improve
at the argument you have heard. Perhaps you may provide
motive to adjust it, or offer extra considerations in defense
of it that assist give an explanation for why you yourself find it viable.
Look for approaches to show which you are doing all your own.On’t attempt to write a philosophy paper from scratch, from starting to give up: you ought to go away lots
of time to devise things out first. Think about the assigned topic for some time, and figure out a likely
thesis and a difficult argument for it to your head. If you’re finding this tough, begin writing rough
sketches of relevant ideas. You’ll throw numerous this material away later, however the act of writing can assist
you to suppose matters thru. When you’re geared up, start to increase a master define on paper. Your
outline ought to display your thesis and your argument in abbreviated form but with maximal logical
readability; attempt to use one line for each logical step of your argument. Make certain it includes capacity
objections and replies, using just more than one lines for every.
You’ll almost honestly discover, as you produce your outline, which you want to revise portions of your
argument or maybe your entire solution. Keep writing sketches of portions of your paper at some point of the
outlining system if it helps. Continue revising the outline till the argument in it's far completely clear
and satisfactory to you. (Try explaining your argument to someone else; if you could’t provide an explanation for it, your
outline needs extra work!) At this factor, write a primary complete draft of your paper out of your define,
that specialize in clarity of the overall shape of your argument.
Once you have got a first draft in hand, hold to revise it, with both the argument’s shape and
your unique phrase selections in mind. Save your drafts as you cross along, so that you can move again in case you
exchange your thoughts. Read your paper out loud or have a chum study it to exercise session which elements of your
argument might confuse or fail to influence the reader and need greater paintings. Be open to changing
your mind and your arguments in any respect degrees of the system, and keep your define updated as you do.
Your final draft need to provide the clearest expression you could manage of your final, well outlined
argument.
philosophical arguments about the Big Questions which are
ideal are extraordinarily hard to assemble, and philosophers
inquisitive about formulating or criticizing such arguments
usually become discussing other questions that can at the beginning
seem pedantic or contrived. These questions motivate
philosophers due to the fact they seem, after investigation, to
be logically related to the Big Questions and to shed
light on them. So, for instance, whilst trying to answer
Big Questions like those above, philosophers might locate
themselves discussing questions like (respectively): When
wouldn't it be morally permissible to push a person into the
path of a dashing trolley? What is a cause? Do I know
that I have palms? Is there an external international? While
arguing approximately these questions may appear stupid or pointless,
the satisfactions of philosophy are often derived from,
first, coming across and explicating how they're logically
connected to the Big Questions, and 2nd, constructing
and protecting philosophical arguments to reply them in
flip. Good philosophy proceeds with modest, careful and
clean steps.
Structuring a Philosophy Paper
Philosophy assignments typically ask you to keep in mind
a few thesis or argument, regularly a thesis or argument that
has been presented via another philosopher (a thesis is
a declare that can be proper or fake). Given this thesis or
argument, you may be asked to do one or more of the
following: give an explanation for it, offer a controversy in guide of
it, offer an objection to it, guard towards an objection
to it, compare the arguments for and towards it, talk
what results it'd have, determine whether
a few different thesis or argument commits one to it (i.E.,
if I regular the alternative thesis or argument, could I be
rationally required to accept this one due to the fact I receive
the other one?), or determine whether or not a few different view
can be held consistently with it. No depend which of
these tasks you are requested to finish, your